Sunday, October 12, 2008

Phenomenology, Women and Re-thinking Religious Experience

Reading Katherine K. Young’s essay, “From the Phenomenology of Religion to Feminism and Women’s Studies,” is encouraging. After having struggled with my own stance towards the role(s) of absolutism and relativism in scholarship last week, I found being introduced to phenomenology helpful.

At the beginning of her article, Young outlines the defining features of the phenomenological approach to religion, stating that it originally involved “synchronic or cross-cultural comparisons and the search for essences, or types (in other circles, this was called comparative religion), but also the historical study of religions with an emphasis on philology and the texts” (Young 18). A lot is said in this one statement.

The idea of searching for “essences” is what first grabbed my attention. I have been reading a lot of David Lewis-Williams lately and thinking about one of his main hypotheses, namely that religious experience is a universal, neurological phenomenon. [Without getting into the details of his argument here, I will just say that I recommend The Mind in the Cave and Inside the Neolithic Mind to anyone interested in neurological explorations of humanity’s history with religious experience]. In spite of the controversy surrounding this hypothesis, I am finding Lewis-Williams’ presentation relevant to my interest in Marian apparitions, particularly in my pursuit of answering why, if this type of religious experience (i.e. the supernatural vision) is indeed available to everyone, is it so heavily stigmatized in contemporary Protestant circles? Is this stigma predominantly rooted in the fact that the apparitions are of a controversial female figure within the Christian tradition? Or is its main locus in the West’s esteem for that which is rational and scientifically verifiable?

What I find so attractive about a phenomenological approach to the study of religion is the way in which it attempts to accommodate and address the extremes of human experience, even if those extremes are classified as “supernatural.” Young says, “because phenomenology allowed for a focus on direct experience, it created scope for scholars to appreciate claims of religious experience by individuals (what became known as the discipline of the psychology of religion)” (Young 20). For me, the idea that an empirically based philosophy can offer the “scope” needed to “appreciate” phenomena like Marian apparitions is incredibly valuable. Admittedly, one could argue that “appreciate” need not equal “scientifically legitimate” and indeed, this has been demonstrated by various psychological studies intent on equating religious experience with pathological experience. Yet, for me, the possibility of a different kind of “appreciation”—one that is capable of employing critical (and practical) methods that do not seek to reduce religious phenomena to “nothing but products of the mind,” one that is capable of “accept[ing] everything that comes into view as tentative fact—cannot be overestimated (Young 19, 23).

At this point, I am reminded of one of the comments that James made on my blog last week. It was well-put and well-taken: “Which is better: (a) because we can't prove something exists we take it not to exist, or (b) because we can't prove something exists we take it to exist. […] Acknowledging that something we cannot prove is real is poor scholarship.” I agree. To proclaim that something is real or fact simply because one is unable to prove otherwise is not responsible. What I am currently grappling with though, is what one is able to say about something that cannot be proven or disproved. If we refuse to subscribe to the “idealism” that Young draws our attention to, namely, categorizing religious experiences as psuedo-psychotic episodes, and instead, treat these phenomena with due complexity, what are we “allowed”/able to say about them (Young 23)? Are we justified in talking about them at all?

Embedded within this week’s descriptions of Gender and Women’s Studies are, I think, several suggestions for how one might answer this last question. Some might rightly shrug this question off, simply claiming their right to study whatever interests them or choosing to avoid what they feel is beyond scholarly discussion in academia. For whatever reason, I am unable to do either of these things and have been thinking about why I feel the need to have a methodological/theoretical justification for studying religious experiences. I am still in the process of formulating my thoughts about this, but I thought that I would include two examples of how Gender and Women’s Studies have been helping me think more about what constitutes a “legitimate” area of study and perhaps more importantly, a “legitimate” mode of study.

The first is derived from Elizabeth A. Clark’s essay, “Engendering the Study of Religion.” In section two, she makes reference to historian Judith Bennett’s argument that gender history “reminds us that many seemingly ‘natural’ ideas about women and men are, in fact, socially constructed” (Clark 237). While it might be a bit of a stretch, I cannot help but think if the same might be said about contemporary Western views on religious experience. Is it possible, in other words, that our ideas of what is “natural” and similarly, what is “not natural,” have been socially constructed? Notably, this question is not meant to revise religious experience as “natural” in the sense of that which is “common.” It is rather, to suggest that experiences like Marian apparitions may be legitimate reasons for academic (and non-academic) communities to revise what they view as “natural” in the sense of that which is “experientially possible” and subsequently, worthy of “serious” scholarship.

The second is derived from David Kinsley’s article, “Women’s Studies in the History of Religions.” In his section on “Engaged Scholarship,” Kinsley makes a point of describing how Women’s Studies has changed the way in which individuals conduct scholarly research. He says, “Women’s studies has also placed a good deal of emphasis on the fact that all scholarship is subjective to some extent. It has raised doubts concerning the possibility (and the desirability) of totally disinterested, objective, detached scholarship. […] The aim is to undertake engaged scholarship—scholarship that is aware of its agenda and pursues it with passion” (Kinsley 10). To take this challenging statement as a license to conduct (and endorse) thoughtlessly biased, non-critical work would be a mistake. But would it be a mistake to read this viewpoint as a theoretical justification for individuals pursuing articulate, intelligent and academically responsible discussions of subjects that extend beyond the realm of what is scientifically verifiable? Clearly I personally do not think that it would…I think that there is definitely more to think about here.

4 comments:

rzwanzig said...

Natalie, we seem to have very different opinions of Young's article! Although I do agree with you that phenomenology is fascinating! I want to comment on your discussion of the categories 'natural' and 'unnatural' being socially constructed. I enjoyed your argument for studying things that can neither be concretely proven nor disproven. This is a very interesting argument by analogy. Just as gender is socially constructed, it could be argued that Western conceptions of religion are as well. You said:

"…Experiences like Marian apparitions may be legitimate reasons for academic (and non-academic) communities to revise what they view as “natural” in the sense of that which is “experientially possible” and subsequently, worthy of “serious” scholarship."

Should these events been taken as a valid realm of experience? Does these mean that the attitude of scientific skepticism should be deconstructed in order to understand these experiences? What would this revision of the term ‘natural’ be? Are there more analogies to be found within the construction of women studies/gender studies theory? I would enjoy hearing you discuss this further.

Emily Springgay said...

Hey Natalie,

I also appreciate phenomenology as a method, and I agree that it can be quite valuable in studies of supernatural religious experiences. I think you have raised some interesting questions as you grapple with the readings and how they relate to your own research. It is an interesting question whether or not scholars ought to theoretically justify their own research interests, especially when dealing with religious phenomena.

One interesting question you asked is:

"Is it possible, in other words, that our ideas of what is “natural” and similarly, what is “not natural,” have been socially constructed?"

Definitely. Rationality and the ability of science have an important place in Western society, and since "supernatural" experiences cannot be well explained scientifically, they tend to be met with skepticism. For some reason, I am reminded of a line from the quasi-documentary, Religulous: "How we define what is crazy or not crazy about religions is ultimately up to how we define crazy." I wonder how Marian apparitions would have been received in the Middle Ages? (or were received - to digress a bit, I would like to know if we have knowledge of any medieval apparitions?) Is what we classify as "natural" or "supernatural" in our society today different from that of medieval Christendom? If these classifications can change in different time periods, or in different cultures, it seems to me that these categories are socially constructed.

Anonymous said...

Natalie, I very much enjoyed reading your blog this week. I was well written, and conveyed the message in a meaningful way. I would like to take-up the following quotation:

"What are we “allowed”/able to say about them (Young 23)? Are we justified in talking about them at all?"

I think that all young scholars are afraid to say something that breaks the limitations imposed by established scholarship. We are also encouraged to think 'outside' the box, to break the limits with pioneering new scholarship. There is a great ambivalence, a significant tension that underlies entrance into academia.

The limits are imposed, presumably, by consensue within any given discipline. They are obvious stated for a very important reason: that scholarship does not run wild. Yet, we are encouraged to test these boundaries, pushed by the competiveness of the field to brea through with novel ideas.

I believe that such limits form part of the regulating function of academia, and that the question of 'what are we allowed to say' is at the heart of scholarship.

Anonymous said...

Natalie, what you wrote really made me think!
I find your inquiry about apparitions and the stigma which surrounds them in protestant settings very fascinating. I think it does have a lot to do with our scientific inclinations.

I wanted to briefly comment about the question of whether or not we can prove something exists as having bearing on its actual existence. Because we can’t prove something exists, does that mean that there is no possibility of it existing? I find it hard to completely dismiss claims of existence. If someone claims they saw something, or felt something, or heard something or..or..or. Maybe my perspective will always differ very much from that of a scholar who works with literature. Working with people (something I think I will always do), forbids me the luxury of denying experiences that I cannot prove through science.

I thoroughly enjoy our discussions, I have grown so much from them, but sometimes, what I find hard about our seminar is that one week we can be so adamant about one point, but the next week start on a new topic and be more lenient about our claims that seemed so steadfast the week before.

Consider this, if I were to tell you that my gender is male, masculine or whatever, you could not prove that. I could be all “woman” or female physically and biologically, but if I identify with being a man, then what science could ever prove that? And this week, we were so firm in our debate that we cannot simply categorize two genders, because not all cultures accept this, and this is not true for everyone, and is not the case just because we say so. But doesn’t this very matter extend beyond the scope of the physical sciences?

I could go on, but I really should stop. Thank you for your insightful entry!